Some Thoughts on Network Ethics

So I know I’ve been mentioned that my two networkologies books are almost done, but I haven’t spoken a lot about how the theory presented in these books goes way beyond what’s up on the blog so far. So here’s a taster.

In his recent reply to my post on SR and Politics, I argue that Levi’s argument that the pressure on SR and OOO to talk about race over frogs is misguided is itself problematic. But I don’t say WHY I think this is the case.

At first it might seem obvious: people are more important than frogs, and racism radically effects people’s lives. Of course, I just assumed that people are more important than frogs. But with OOO and SR, this seemingly simple anthopocentric gesture becomes problematic. If OOO  works to put all objects on the same level, why are people more important than frogs? Isn’t this precisely the sort of thinking we’re working to get rid of? Isn’t the whole point of the Latour litanies that its important to view neoplatonism and flowers as being on fundamentally the same ontological level?

Of course, then the question becomes why. Why is it so important to us to make ontology, and potentially ethics, flat? Why do we want so badly to move beyond our Cartesian and Kantian heritage? Ok, we want to secularize our philosophy, get rid of the residual religiosity in us. Or at least, that would SEEM to be the reason. Ultimately, Deleuze’s desire for a flat ontology is that he follows on Nietzsche’s desire for a non-otherwordly philosophy. And values. The push for a this worldly philosophy was originally supposed to be about ethics, right? I wonder, is that still why a flat ontology and lack of transcendence is important to us all?

So, let me talk about Network Ethics a bit. In my nearly complete manifesto book, an entire third of the text is devoted to network ethics. And within network ethics, there is only one standard of value: complexity. This value is designed as something which applies to human, living, and non-living systems. Here’s a quickie version of why.

A Quick Intro to Some Principles from Network Ethics

All valuation is done by conscious organisms. And these organisms value because they have been evolved to value, and they have been evolved to value one thing: complexity. For by acting in a manner that they believe will allow them to increase in complexity (to continue living, growing, and developing), organisms value complexity. Evolution, however, does not ‘value’ (more on this sort of valuation) merely complexity, but robustness, that is, the ability to make complexity increase in a sustainable manner. This is why robustness, which is composed of both complexity and sustainability, is essential for network ethics. Organisms value complexity, but the overall goal of evolution is to create organisms that value robustness. The gap between one state and the other, the valuation of complexity and that of robustness, is the separation between evolution as it is and evolution as it strives to be.

We cannot say that ‘evolution’ truly values in the ways that organisms value, however. An evolutionary population is known in network ethics as a plex, a collective entity which is quasi-living, for it resembles living organisms in many ways, but can do so only when supported by living organisms. An evolutionary population is a plex, just as a language is a plex. There are many types of plexes, for example, memeplexes, semeplexes, etc.

An evolutionary population therefore doesn’t value robustness, but rather, can be said to quasi-values robustness. This quasi-valuation indicates the manner in which the collective desire of the population exceeds the desire of the individual agents within that population in a manner which precisely indicates the ‘part exceeds the whole’ structure which is indicative of the definition of complexity itself. For complexity is precisely that within wholes which exceeds their parts.

Metaleptics is the discipline within network ethics which works to understand the manner in which emergence within quasi-liviing populations allows organisms to ‘pick themselves up by their own bootstraps’ by means of evolution. Metaleptics attempts to describe the manner in which the quasi-valuation of robustness by evolution provides an immanent telos to evolution from complexity to robustness. This telos is not absolute or transcendent, but immanent to the very structure of the evolutionary process itself.

Evolution has three forms: material, natural, and cultural. Material evolution occurs when meta-stable energetic conditions give rise to increasing material complexity. While material systems do not value, we can say that material evolution occurs when material systems increase in complexity, because these systems then approach the realm of value exhibited by conscious (and most often living) organisms. In this sense, material evolution proto-values complexity, just as organisms in natural evolutionary populations value complexity, and natural evolutionary populations quasi-value robustness. Cultural evolution is a much more difficult topic, to be discussed at a later date.

The point is that according to network ethics, in a chain of logic to be described another time, the fundamental maxim is as follows: “Let all your networks operate at maximum robustness.” This is an immanent, flat, and anti-transcendent ethical doctrine. It is justified by the discipline of metaleptics, and employed by the discipline of practics to specific situations. Within this maxim, robustness should be understood as sustainable complexity, and complexity as the potential to produce greater complexity in the future (the discussion of potential should also be relegated to another time).

Robustness and complexity are not necessarily anthropocentric values. They value anything which gives rise to a greater intensity within what is. Complexity is necessarily mental and material, because in order for there to be one, there needs to be the other, as these are two sides of the same (in the sense in which Spinoza speaks of mind and matter as two ways of looking at substance). A human mind, for example, is not some Cartesian entity floating in a void. It is only by means of the material complexity of the human brain that the mental complexity of the human mind could come about, for human minds and brains are two aspects of the same.

Nevertheless, to ask the question of value, and ethics with it, is to always be within a realm which privileges humans, if simply because we are the phenomenon which values the most complexly.

Also, when the fundamental maxim of network ethics speaks of ‘your networks’, ‘your’ should be understood to mean all the networks in your world, if in differing degrees. For in fact, all networks are your networks, for each and every network is a refraction of all the others with which it is related. That said, as Whitehead has argued, because there is extension within the universe, giving rise to time and space, each entity in the universe is ‘ranked’ in ‘relevance’ to each other by the very structure of the universe itself. Mars is more relevant to me than Alpha Centuri, for example. And so, while both are still ‘my networks’, the one which is more relevant to me is mine in a stronger sense.

I should strive to increase the robustness of all my networks, because this is the manner in which I will increase not only my own robustness (for all networks are connected, if differently), but that of the system as a whole within which I exist. Wanting to increase the robustness of the world in which I exist is the most selfish and most altruistic way to relate to that world. It is in fact to be in sync with the immanent order of that world, and to value that which has allowed you to value in the first place, namely, robustness.

In order to ‘let’ your networks operate at maximum robustness, however, you must learn about yourself and the world and the ways in which they are interconnected. Understanding the immanent order of the world, that which gave rise to valuation, is what allows us to promote robustness. It is in this manner that network ethics proposes something quite similar to what Spinoza called the ‘intellectual love of god’ as its primary ethical goal. This goal is also quite similar to that of the ancient Stoics, a clear influence on Spinoza’s immanent ethics, as well as Nietzsche’s own attempt to create a ‘this-worldly ethics’. Linking this to genealogy is the project of metaleptics, and it is in this manner that the project of network ethics works to ground itself by valuing itself, and thereby ‘eating its own tail’, so to speak.

Practics requires that we apply network ethics. And this is why I think it is possible to say that having OOO and SR deal with racism before frogs is because of a philosophical system of value which is flat, immanent, and not classicly anthropocentric. Or as Steve Schaviro has lately put forth, they are anthropomorphic but not anthropocentric.

The fine-toothed implications of these statements are being worked out at length in my manifesto book, which will be done quite soon. I’m going to be out of the country for July, but back at work on this in August, and I see no reason why the entire text won’t be done by then.

Advertisements

~ by chris on June 30, 2010.

2 Responses to “Some Thoughts on Network Ethics”

  1. […] Uncategorized Leave a Comment  Over at Networkologies Vitale has a post up discussing his network ethics. I won’t get into Vitale’s network ethics here, but I did want to make a few remarks […]

  2. […] Some Thoughts on Network Ethics […]

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out / Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out / Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out / Change )

Google+ photo

You are commenting using your Google+ account. Log Out / Change )

Connecting to %s

 
%d bloggers like this: